A Profusion Of Place | Part I: Of Unity And Philosophy
by Steven Gussman
1Physicist Max Tegmark's Our Mathematical Universe is a hodge-podge, part popular astronomy book, part memoir, and part creative playground for exploring new ideas. His account of mainstream physics and astronomy sheds light on the subject in a unique way, and I appreciate that he is willing to directly recognize the obvious big questions.2 The book ultimately revolves around Tegmark's unlikely idea of the most expansive multiverse imaginable, and several arguments from fundamental physics to cognitive psychology are employed to get there. Like many of us, Tegmark is dissatisfied with standard quantum physics, but he (and increasingly his colleagues in physics) embraces a cure that's worse than the disease in the Everettian “many worlds” multiverse interpretation, which simply moves the central problem without answering it.3 By taking advantage of the most simple models of recent scientific ideas in need of more empirical evidence (such as quantum foundations and inflationary cosmology), Tegmark is able to assume an unimaginable proliferation of worlds.4 The namesake of the book is Tegmark's hypothesis that the physical universe is nothing but bare mathematics, an argument he makes by playing a bait and switch with the two terms.5 Given the ever-increasing number of universes this book argues in favor of, I see my role as culling things back down. In the present essay, I will be addressing the general arguments for the existence of a multiverse.
1Physicist Max Tegmark's Our Mathematical Universe is a hodge-podge, part popular astronomy book, part memoir, and part creative playground for exploring new ideas. His account of mainstream physics and astronomy sheds light on the subject in a unique way, and I appreciate that he is willing to directly recognize the obvious big questions.2 The book ultimately revolves around Tegmark's unlikely idea of the most expansive multiverse imaginable, and several arguments from fundamental physics to cognitive psychology are employed to get there. Like many of us, Tegmark is dissatisfied with standard quantum physics, but he (and increasingly his colleagues in physics) embraces a cure that's worse than the disease in the Everettian “many worlds” multiverse interpretation, which simply moves the central problem without answering it.3 By taking advantage of the most simple models of recent scientific ideas in need of more empirical evidence (such as quantum foundations and inflationary cosmology), Tegmark is able to assume an unimaginable proliferation of worlds.4 The namesake of the book is Tegmark's hypothesis that the physical universe is nothing but bare mathematics, an argument he makes by playing a bait and switch with the two terms.5 Given the ever-increasing number of universes this book argues in favor of, I see my role as culling things back down. In the present essay, I will be addressing the general arguments for the existence of a multiverse.
Our Mathematical Universe is
really a book about multiverses, as every argument that Tegmark makes
leads to another multiverse. Tegmark has come up with a very useful
taxonomy of multiverses. The level-I multiverse
is what most of us simply call the universe
(albeit modified by the rather premature assumptions of both an
infinite volume of spacetime and infinite matter to fill it, all
seeded with different initial conditions by quantum-random
fluctuations just prior to the big bang). Here, anything that can
occur according to the ordinary laws of classical physics does
occur somewhere because given infinite matter, space, and time, even
the rarest events must happen. The level-II multiverse
comes from the premature assumptions that inflation occurred before
the big bang (rather than immediately after, as the theory originally
intended) and that inflation is an eternal event, constantly spawning
off new level-I multiverses such as our own, separated by an
exponentially expanding field of meta-space called the inflaton.6
The level-III multiverse
is the multiverse associated with quantum physicist Hugh Everett's
many worlds interpretation
of quantum physics—the idea that since quantum physics only ever
yields probabilistic (rather than classically deterministic)
solutions to physics problems, it is actually telling us that each of
the possible outcomes does
occur somewhere. Finally, most hypothetical of all, the level-IV
multiverse is Tegmark's own
contribution to the proliferation of worlds, and it is related to his
idea that he calls the mathematical universe hypothesis,
which states that physical reality is itself nothing but abstract
mathematics, and so the level-IV multiverse emerges from the fact
that Tegmark cannot explain why only some
math seems to describe our universe, which Tegmark takes as a
prediction that all
mathematical structures exist as separate universes governed by those
maths. Needless to say, many level-IV universes contain level-II
universes (as long as they contain eternal inflation—indeed, they
may contain much worse!), all level-II universes contain a level-III
multiverse, and all level-III universes contain a level-I
multiverse.7
Tegmark seems almost religiously in awe of this infinitude of
worlds, which may say more about what makes him tick than the Cosmos.
Indeed, Tegmark writes, “...
we may find ourselves inhabiting a reality grander than our ancestors
imagined in their wildest dreams.”8
One has to wonder if that wasn't for good reason—as Carl Sagan
warns, “Imagination will often carry us to worlds that never were.
But without it, we go nowhere.”9
To start with, I will note that semantic arguments aren't based on deep philosophical disagreements, and so I will spend little time on the debate between whether there can be more than one “universe”, by definition. What is interesting is whether reality really looks like several (or infinitely many) copies of what we now think of as our “universe”, or just the one as was classically thought. The “universe” is already known to be bigger than the observable universe (which consists of a spherical particle horizon with us at the center, and is always “expanding” in the sense that photons from further and further away are always finally reaching us from out in the universe as time permits).10 Any universe with a finite speed limit for information to travel will only be partially detectable to an observer based on where they are located and how old their universe is. Thus, a multi-observable-universe is trivially true, though no one would consider this an actual multiverse, just a limit on the interactions between any sufficiently far away portions of a single universe (that is to say that observable universes are just infinitely many overlapping particle horizons—nothing but reference frames—not distinct structures or objects).11 Astronomer and philosopher of science, Carl Sagan preferred the singular use of “universe”, but in truth, it wouldn't be the first time a scientific concept had outgrown its literal meaning by being too presumptuous—“atom” is famously Greek for “indivisible”, and yet it turns out that the atoms of the periodic table are not elementary particles, but are instead made up of (and mediated by) lower level objects such as electrons, quarks, photons, and gluons.12 Tegmark writes, “... some... use the phrase... 'the universe,' to mean everything that exists, in which case, by definition, there can't be any parallel universes.”13 Yet semantically, I can't help but think that it would only be in keeping with tradition to have multiple “universes” just as we have divisible “indivisibles”.
To start with, I will note that semantic arguments aren't based on deep philosophical disagreements, and so I will spend little time on the debate between whether there can be more than one “universe”, by definition. What is interesting is whether reality really looks like several (or infinitely many) copies of what we now think of as our “universe”, or just the one as was classically thought. The “universe” is already known to be bigger than the observable universe (which consists of a spherical particle horizon with us at the center, and is always “expanding” in the sense that photons from further and further away are always finally reaching us from out in the universe as time permits).10 Any universe with a finite speed limit for information to travel will only be partially detectable to an observer based on where they are located and how old their universe is. Thus, a multi-observable-universe is trivially true, though no one would consider this an actual multiverse, just a limit on the interactions between any sufficiently far away portions of a single universe (that is to say that observable universes are just infinitely many overlapping particle horizons—nothing but reference frames—not distinct structures or objects).11 Astronomer and philosopher of science, Carl Sagan preferred the singular use of “universe”, but in truth, it wouldn't be the first time a scientific concept had outgrown its literal meaning by being too presumptuous—“atom” is famously Greek for “indivisible”, and yet it turns out that the atoms of the periodic table are not elementary particles, but are instead made up of (and mediated by) lower level objects such as electrons, quarks, photons, and gluons.12 Tegmark writes, “... some... use the phrase... 'the universe,' to mean everything that exists, in which case, by definition, there can't be any parallel universes.”13 Yet semantically, I can't help but think that it would only be in keeping with tradition to have multiple “universes” just as we have divisible “indivisibles”.
The
assumption that our universe consists of infinite space and time,
containing infinite matter-energy is on surprisingly weak footing
considering how well-subscribed it seems to be among cosmologists.
Quantum Engineer Seth Lloyd (a collaborator of Tegmark's) claims,
“The same observations that establish the detailed history of the
universe imply that the observed cosmos is a vanishingly small
fraction of an infinite universe... Beyond the horizon of our
observation lies more of the same—space filled with galaxies
stretching on forever... All but an infinitesimal fraction of the
universe is unknowable.”14
But he doesn't explain what that theory which predicts the
infinities is—it looks to me like the best (indeed one of the only)
arguments in favor of it seems to be that it's a simple assumption in
lieu of evidence pointing in any particular direction (and in place
of much theoretical motivation towards a serious answer at all).15 This is a situation in which astronomers' Copernican
Principle (a heuristic, not a
physical law), which states that local observations should be taken
to be ordinary, runs awry.16
It is true that historically, cosmology and physics were marred by
the idea that we were special—the heavens above were supposed to
have followed different, more perfect laws than our lowly, secular
Earth, and it was assumed that Earth was the center of the solar
system which was assumed to be the center of the universe. It turns
out that the laws of physics are the same everywhere in the universe
and that Earth isn't the center of the solar system, which isn't the
center of the Milky Way galaxy, which isn't at the center of the
universe. But replacing one dogmatic assumption with its reverse
isn't the right solution—the solution is to always apply scrutiny
and follow the evidence. Assumptions, hypotheses, and conjectures
should be taken with a grain of salt when they have little to no
empirical confirmation behind them. We know our universe is either
flat, or very large if
it is another geometry which curves back on itself. For the universe
to be flat, it almost certainly must be infinite, but there is little
reason to think that the universe is flat and infinite rather than
large, curved, and finite to allow for the flatness observed on
scales we have already confirmed).17
In fact, Tegmark admits that the minimum size of a non-flat universe
given our cosmic microwave background (CMB) measurements only requires 100 level-I universes!18
If this is true, his level-I multiverse is dead in the water. A
universe 100 times the size of our observable universe is very
different than his normal
level-I argument–it merely increases our universe's known number of
galaxies, stars, and planets by a factor of 100, which can scarcely
be called a “multiverse”. It is indeed just a universe with
completely distinct galaxies, stars, and planets with no expected
doppelgangers, uncanny similarities, or 'loss of determinism' (it is
exactly what one ordinarily pictures deep space to be like).19
It
seems Tegmark's best evidence is the claim that the infinity
assumption is the “simplest” model; as in all such cases, it
seems we lack enough information to leave equipoise and construct
grand ideas around weak foundations. Infinite
flatness filled with uniform matter is a fine assumption to make in
the meantime, given it may simplify our models and calculations, but
taking it so seriously as to assume that it actually means there is
an infinite level-I multiverse is going too far. In fact, one of the
ways in which Tegmark contradicts himself is to lean on arguments
such as this, while at another point arguing that he doesn't think
infinity exists at all, even in mathematics—he thinks that there is
some maximum quantity and precision. Tegmark claims to both believe
in the cosmological infinity-assumption and that
infinity doesn't exist (even pointing out that this will tame much of
the outlandish ideas I'm opposing in the present work).20
I will add to his skepticism a strange contradiction in mainstream
physics: when infinite quantities show up as the results of physics
calculations (such as the infinitely curved spacetime / infinite
density at a black hole singularity), it is typically understood as a
sign that the theory is “breaking down” (that this is an
approximate theory being used outside of its effective domain).21
Yet in cosmology, Tegmark makes it seem fairly customary to
nonchalantly assume infinite spacetime and matter in the simplest
models. Considering this infinity didn't even come out of an
equation, but is simply an assumption, it ought to be taken even less
seriously by comparison. Given
that the big bang is often considered the mechanism for birthing our
universe, it's worth wondering how realistic it is to suppose that
not only a whole lot of
matter occupied the same subatomic spot, but infinite
matter, most of which
subsequently expanded away. It all smacks of attempting to take
unfinished theories further than they can reasonably be expected to
go, of pretending all scientific progress ends right now, and so we
have to make due with only our current equations and observations.
Strangely, Tegmark insists that
multiverses are the predictions of
theories.22
But predictions are based on precise mathematical solutions—the
extent to which these theories can be made to speak of multiverses
are just tantalizing little hints at best ('maybe quantum
superpositions correlate to entire doppelganger universes', 'maybe
inflation goes on forever and gives rises to many universes', 'maybe
the reason we haven't yet explained the values of physical constants
is because there exist all sorts of universes with all manner of
physical constants', etc.). These are not what
we traditionally call scientific predictions: they're hand-waving
possibilities. Strangely, Tegmark says that the scientific method is
in part about making “... predictions from assumptions...”, and
even calls theories “... a collection of assumptions...”. While
he may have been simply speaking to the provisional nature of
knowledge, it is interesting when juxtaposed with the fact that he
sees mulitverses as “predictions of theories”, when he's actually
making the prediction from an empirically verified theory plus
an entirely un-empirically
verified assumption (like that of infinite space and matter).23
While it may be fun to think about doppelgangers of oneself in a far
away patch of spacetime, there is very little reason to think it is
actually the case. We ought to remain agnostic as to whether the
universe is truly flat at the largest scale, is infinite in scale,
and contains infinite matter-energy until better evidence comes in,
and that means refraining from taking the more outlandish
consequences of an infinite multiverse too seriously.24
Tegmark employs general arguments in favor of multiverses on multiple occasions. The first such case that I want to address, which one might call the historical induction argument, is simply the observation that we have historically thought the universe were smaller than it would later turn out to be (first our solar system, then our galaxy), and so perhaps we are making this mistake once more.25 However, it's difficult to see how this could have historically been any different—conservatism grounds things in what is currently known and progress shows finally that there really is something new. Strange indeed it would be if historically, things significantly shrank, because one needs a reason to believe there are more things and needn't one to think that there exists only what already meets the eye. Even so, this is a flimsy argument, as a trend such as “the Cosmos turns out to be larger than we expected” needs to terminate somewhere. Indeed, this argument could even be used against Tegmark's meager four-tiered multiverse (though barely, as we shall see) to say, why not more?
Tegmark employs general arguments in favor of multiverses on multiple occasions. The first such case that I want to address, which one might call the historical induction argument, is simply the observation that we have historically thought the universe were smaller than it would later turn out to be (first our solar system, then our galaxy), and so perhaps we are making this mistake once more.25 However, it's difficult to see how this could have historically been any different—conservatism grounds things in what is currently known and progress shows finally that there really is something new. Strange indeed it would be if historically, things significantly shrank, because one needs a reason to believe there are more things and needn't one to think that there exists only what already meets the eye. Even so, this is a flimsy argument, as a trend such as “the Cosmos turns out to be larger than we expected” needs to terminate somewhere. Indeed, this argument could even be used against Tegmark's meager four-tiered multiverse (though barely, as we shall see) to say, why not more?
Another
general argument in favor of multiverses is The
Anthropic Principle which
is invoked so as to explain so-called “fine-tuning”, which
Tegmark defines as “Physical
constants in the effective laws having values in a very narrow range
allowing life...”.26
In general, The
Anthropic Principle simply states that if life occurs rarely in the
universe, then we are in that rare region, for as unlikely as it is,
we're clearly alive! One can extend that argument in favor of a
multiverse by arguing that if the (seemingly) fundamental physical
constants are narrowly tuned to be conducive to life, then there must
exist a multiverse of universes with different physical constants
(most of these not conducive to life), and we only find ourselves in
a rare life-bearing universe because, again, we're clearly alive.27 Putting aside the irony that most physicists who buy into these
kinds of arguments also pay lip-service to The Copernican
Principle (the assumption that
there is nothing
special about our place in the universe), the
problem is that one could make this argument for anything
—and
if they did, it would probably have kept us from some discoveries we
have made.28
In fact, all
questions
we have historically answered could have been instead answered the
same way. Why doesn't retroactively doing so suffice? Doesn't it
become a mystery why we should have ever been able to come up with
singular answers to any
scientific questions, if an inference to infinite variety without
special evidence suffices? As long as you postulate that everything
exists,
you can argue that it's not so strange that what you are currently
observing exists. It's not a deeply clever idea like Darwinian
evolution, because it's missing the selection and mutation portions.29
Historically, allowing this kind of explanation would have stalled
out scientific understanding a long time ago—for example: the
answer to “why do people generally enjoy sex?” cannot be “because
there exist both people who do and don't enjoy sex, but we've only
tended to meet the former”.30
Put this way, it's clear that the “answer” is simply a
restatement of the observation, not an explanation of it! Having not
accepted such answers, Darwin,Wallace, and their disciples eventually
realized that people generally enjoy sex because those who do are
more likely to produce kin and those kin are in turn more likely by
inheritance to enjoy sex.31
This example does invoke a diversity of kinds of organisms (though
mechanisms needn't generally), but with two crucial components which
change it from a casual restatement of the question: a mechanism for
generating variation (genetic mutation during replication) and a
selection pressure biasing the proliferation of some outcomes rather
than others over time (natural / sexual / artificial selection).
Most multiverse ideas have neither—they simply state infinite
variation with no mechanism for generating such a plethora of worlds
and no selection of some over others to produce a non-random
outcome.32
Evolution is a far-cry from attempting to explain the diversity of
life by saying that all
imaginable
life-forms exist somewhere, and so the fact that we see these ones
just means we're near these ones.33
This kind of thinking gets rid of the need for any mechanism at
all—if my friend gets an A on a test, rather than posit that he
studied hard or cheated and adjudicate between the likelihood of
these with empirical evidence, I can just assume he took the test
infinitely many times, got every possible grade, and I must have just
happened to have been around for one of the times where he got an A.34
Even if we allow this kind of theoretical reasoning, it's not
obvious why, in the absence of adjudicating empirical evidence, we
should choose to interpret it as statistical (all possible universes
exist, and we are in a rare life-supporting one by The Anthropic
Principle) rather than as probabilistic (many possible configurations
for our one universe could
have
existed, and a relatively unlikely life-supporting one is the one
that happens to, by The Anthropic Principle).35
On top of all of this, it is not unlikely that a true theory of
everything would be inherently much more restrictive on the allegedly
turn-able knobs that are (or aren't?) the fundamental physical
constants.36
Why is it thought that particles' masses and interaction strengths
could be otherwise (surely something
in
our universe must be foundational)? This would seem to throw
induction out the window.37
The idea that if the mathematics of our equations doesn't explicitly
limit the domain of input, then those situations with those inputs
must exist somewhere is not logical, particularly when we know we
don't have a fundamental theory, only approximate theories of
different facets of some grand underlying theory of everything.38
We simply don't look at Newton's law of gravitation, F = GMm/r2
and think of the universal gravitational constant G as a variable
without serious evidence that this is the case.39
In short, I'm not really bothered by the idea that everything that's
physically possible doesn't necessarily occur, or hasn't, or
won't—why should it all? This is the difference between the actual
and the possible. It's not obvious why it's not the case that
certain relationships and ratios are true physical constants and so
turning one knob adjusts the others to compensate and yields the same
universe (this is like the difference between shrinking an object by
having it be made of less matter versus shrinking the size of the
constituent particles themselves). Tegmark compares the classical
physicists' idea of constrained fundamental constants to older
physicists' ideas that certain values in our solar system were
fundamental in the sense that they required deep explanations (such
as planetary mass or radii).40
But while it's true that the discovery that there are many planets
throughout the universe (of many different orbits, masses, and radii)
disabuses us of any suspicion that our solar system's particular
orbital properties are universally foundational, our understanding of
physics does actually provide some understanding as to the realistic
ranges of masses, radii, and orbital distances of bodies of certain
materials.41
Furthermore, fine-tuning arguments assume we know what the values of
physical constants ought to be ahead of time (from common-sense, not
theoretical prediction), and that changing those values by a small
amount should not have big consequences if there is a single
universe. I would like to invoke chaos
theory
as a possible alternative explanation for the fact that small changes in
fundamental constants seem to predict the vanishing of biology.42
If the roll of a die of certain common materials against surfaces of
other certain materials can be found to yield quite sensitive
results, why shouldn't cosmological evolution be sensitive to even
subtle changes in fundamental constants?43
The universe is by definition the
most
complex system—it is the sum total cause-and-effect of all of
reality—would it be any wonder that facets of this system turned
out to be “chaotic” in this sense?44
Why should we test any ideas against observations as a measurement
of theoretical success if we thought that any approximation shouldn't
matter much to the evolution of the universe? No one thinks that
finding such “chaotic” systems as the die-roll mentioned above
requires hypothesizing a multiverse, so why should it be invoked for
a universe that is “chaotic” in this sense, when we already know
many of its isolated constituent subsystems to be?45
Why should we even predict, measure, and use physical constants in
our equations (not to mention check predictions from theories of
cosmological history) if changing the fundamental constants should be
assumed not to have much effect on cosmic evolution (the output of
the equations)?46
And all of that is without even asking the question of what is meant
by a “small” change to a fundamental constant. Concepts such as
large and small are subject to spatial relativity (they only make
sense in a particular reference frame; “smaller” than
what?).
I would argue that when it comes to physical constants, we have no
such reference frame. It is not obvious why a range of 1-34% (which
is itself naively imprecise) should be considered “small”, let
alone why the same percentage of change would be considered “small”
for all constants.47
Note, too that speaking in terms of percents does not actually
normalize the problem: there is no reason that 150% or -25% ought to
be considered anymore unrealistic an alternative version of the value
than 0% to 100%; this is just a way of speaking about any arbitrary
value in terms of the observed value. In fact, the only way I can
think to propose to scientifically figure out what constitutes a
“small” change to a physical constant would be to define
it
by the largest change that doesn't
have large ramifications for predictions (such as the impossibility
of life), which completely turns the idea of “fine-tuning” on its
head. Could
it be that properties of the universe now considered fundamental
aren't? Sure. But that doesn't tell us that any of them actually
aren't, much less which. At the end of the day, calling these values
“fine-tuned” begs the question that The Anthropic Principle
purports to answer; it may be that such things can't be fine-tuned
which were never “tuned” in the first place.48
The Anthropic Principle / fine-tuning multiverse is possible,
in that it is a coherent hypothesis, but short very extraordinary
empirical evidence, this kind of cop-out should be the last
place
we look to hang our hats, because it's so convenient as to leave one
prematurely satisfied. In
short, Tegmark's plethora of arguments in favor of multiverses can
seem like a case of quantity over quality, particularly in the case
of general arguments.
Then
there is the measure problem.49
In mathematics, it is sometimes argued that there are differently
sized infinities—the most famous example being that there is a
larger infinity of integers than there are odd
integers (as only half of all integers are odd).50
In multiverse cosmology, thinkers are wondering how to count the
different universes, as they contain no inherent order, and order
matters when approximating the convergence of an infinite sum.51
There is a hope that the measure problem can be solved in such a way
as to yield the same probability distribution as in quantum physics
superpositions.52
Some cosmologists consider this number a sort of “amount” of
reality (where universes of “greater measure” are in some sense
“more real”).53
Call me classical, but I think that real or fake is entirely the
same as true or false, physical or un-physical, natural or
supernatural, actual or actually not—whether or not something is
real is a completely binary property. What this says to me is that
if there really is a relationship between classical multiverses and
the quantum multiverse, then because each universe's measure is a
rational number (because each universe exists in some integer number
of duplicate universes divided by some integer number of total
universes, both of which may be different infinities), then quantum
probabilities must also
be rational numbers and therefore this continuous facet of quantum
theory must be quantized. In other words, if this relationship were
true and the measure problem solved, quantum mechanics would be due
for an upgrade to only allowing rational probabilities assigned by
its probability distributions.54
Something about this jives nicely with Tegmark's later arguments
against infinity and the continuum. In the meantime, considering how
speculative these ideas are, it seems more likely that the
fact that our current
well-motivated idea of probability densities allows the prediction of
irrational probabilities for measurement outcomes is telling us that
it probably can't be the same thing as the rational value of the
“measure” of a universe in a multiverse.
On falsifiability, I am only
partially persuaded by Tegmark's arguments against pure Popperian
epistemology. A common argument against any scientific hypothesis is
that it isn't actually a scientific hypothesis (falsification
is Karl Popper's strict idea that a scientific hypothesis
must be falsifiable—it must make clear predictions which can be
shown to be false based on empirical observation through
experiment).55
I agree with Tegmark that this is perhaps too narrow in the sense
that we should be defining scientific hypotheses as ideas which could
describe reality (imposing any other restrictions would be, to
borrow a term from Tegmark, “human baggage”).56
There is a fear in any philosopher of science: what if there
actually existed two physical phenomena which always cancel each
other out in every single case, and so never have any observable
effects; in what sense can it be said that they really are, or really
are not happening? The most I can do to console you is to say that
this is no different than the realization that every time you say
“3”, you're actually saying “3 + (0 * x)” (among many other
equations), that is to say that they are isomorphic (totally
equivalent).57 But I suspect something more is true about physical reality—most
(and I would ultimately conjecture all)
different hypotheses / theories have some
different prediction
(and at the very least, even if there are unobservables, we don't yet
have criteria for deciding which phenomena are in that class). Call
it the exclusivity
conjecture in
philosophy of science.58
This is to claim that differences in explanation will always
make different predictions in some way (another way of putting
this is that different real mechanisms will always leave some unique
information signature on the universe). This trivializes the whole
argument because while I prefer Tegmark's definition of a
scientific hypothesis (science is the description of reality, not the
strictly falsifiable description of reality, though we hope that this
is the case for epistemology's sake), I still emphasize the need for
empirical evidence in support of a theory or predicted phenomenon. I
take Tegmark's point that if a theory makes 10 predictions, one of
which is in principle unobservable, and the other nine are confirmed
by empirical evidence, then we ought to take the 10th
seriously.59
But that does not mean believing this phenomenon as strongly
as the others—all scientific knowledge is provisional—it may be
that some new theory will predict the same nine observable phenomena,
and not the 10th unobservable one (and perhaps new
observable phenomena that are themselves confirmed).60
For this reason, the only way the certainty of an unobservable
prediction could grow is slowly as time goes on with no new theory to
supplant the one which makes that prediction. My sympathy with both
Tegmark and his falsifiability
critics comes from different directions than those factions; it's a
conjecture about nature (that may be wrong), not a statement on what
scientists are allowed to consider. Tegmark is right ontologically
(we don't know for sure that reality actually follows such rules that
everything that exists is observable in principle to us), and his
critics are right epistemologically (it is unfortunately just a fact
that we cannot have a good reason to believe we're in possession of a
true ontological description without the concept of falsifiability
testing). By example,
Tegmark tries to argue that General Relativity's successes in
empirical prediction leads it to be taken seriously where we don't
yet have empirical confirmation—but I would rebut that it is
crucial that we
don't yet have it, and that we therefore have only probabilistic
knowledge. For example, gravitational waves were taken more
seriously after Nobel-prize winning circumstantial evidence was shown
that co-orbiting pulsars lost energy in just the way this phenomenon
predicted.61
Then in 2015 (verified and announced in 2016), when gravitational
waves were at last directly
detected, despite most physicists already believing they existed, the
team at LIGO was also awarded the Nobel prize in physics (it's worth
mentioning that Einstein never even got a Nobel Prize for either
theory of relativity, though there is more to that story).62
Apparently something
about directly
observing this phenomenon we were all totally sure about was of
particular importance. Perhaps multiverses are something we can
believe in, but simply not something we can award Nobel prizes for.
Puzzlingly, Tegmark specifically mentions black hole interiors as an
example of an unobservable prediction to take seriously, but most
think General Relativity breaks down at these singularities and
doesn't help
describe it, much!63
How a theory breaks down can be telling, but it's not making a
strong prediction, much less one that can be believed without
empirical evidence. Nevertheless, I remain only a
soft-Popperian because the central problem here is that while I
suspect that there is no such thing as an unobservable phenomenon,
there may well be, and I do not want to restrict our scientific
understanding of the world—science ought to describe reality as
best we can, with whatever reliable tools we can, and with no
arbitrary restrictions. That said, I am on the side of the
Popperians in practice, as I am extremely skeptical of anyone
claiming an unobservable phenomenon.64
Any phenomenon should be assumed to be in principle
observable unless a lot of time and work goes by without
anyone being able to figure out what kind of a signal it might leave
for us to measure. Any time an
observation “can be interpreted as evidence of” multiple
different competing hypotheses, it's just not a specific enough
observation to be empirical evidence for any of them.65
One needs evidence that can differentiate
between multiple
competing explanations. This new idea that multiple explanations are
going to be equally compatible is wrong-headed, and is creating
confusion throughout physics all the way down to quantum foundations.
Despite all of the anti-Popperians' claims, many experimentalists
(and even theoreticians) have indeed been attempting to come up with
possible observations and experiments which could shed light on
whether or not a particular multiverse exists. In this light, the
theoreticians who claim unobservable multiverses (and this almost
only happens with multiverses) seem to be hiding from the
challenge that everyone else in history's ideas have been subjected
to: empirical evidence. I am in agreement with the Popperians that
there is something deeply defeatist with assuming any scientific
hypothesis is unobservable in principle, right out of the gate
(especially if one is not an experimentalist anyway!).
At this time, I will segue
from the topic of physics to that of the sociology of physicists, for
a hypothesis of my own: I predict that, absent obvious evidence (as
is the current situation with most data pertaining to multiverses),
more politically conservative physicists will tend to favor the tight
economical view that a better understanding of fundamental physics
will constrain the fundamental constants more apparently, and that
politically liberal (and especially progressive) physicists will tend
to favor large, expansive, and diverse multiverses. The assumption
here is that political orientation is downstream from general
philosophical orientation, which is likely at least statistically
true; really, the reason that the same physicist is predicted to be
more likely than his counterparts to favor multiverses and
vote for Barack Obama (or favor a singular universe and vote
for Ronald Reagan) is because they are philosophically conservative
or liberal / progressive. That is, I'm arguing that it is a common
cause (philosophical orientation) that leads to both political and
physical orientation (in the absence of evidence one way or the other
on a given physics question), not political orientation that directly
causes physical orientation. Without making specific predictions
about the correlation between a physicist's politics and multiverse
preferences, Brian Greene seems to recognize the philosophical
conflict of visions beneath the debate, writing, “... the anthropic
principle... is a perspective that is diametrically opposed to the
dream of a rigid, fully predictive, unified theory in which things
are the way they are because the universe could not be otherwise.
Rather than being the epitome of poetic grace in which everything
fits together with inflexible elegance, the multiverse and the
anthropic principle paints a picture of a wildly excessive collection
of universes with an insatiable appetite for variety.”66
Furthermore, coupling this hypothesis with the fact that there are
more Democrat academics than Republican academics in every field (in
physics, the ratio is 6.21), we are expected to get a skewed popular
opinion (that may masquerade as a “scientific consensus” rather
than an ordinary consensus), which will reflect in polls like those
Tegmark has informally gathered at at least one conference.67
Further yet, because left-leaning people tend to be more creative
and I assume are likely more interested in educating the public, I
suspect that this effect will be amplified further among popular book
and column writers (and science popularizers, more generally). Both
Becker and Carroll have cited a sort of “ick factor” as a lame
counterargument they see to the idea of multiverses, which could be
interpreted as a sort of conservative reaction (and both Becker and
Carroll are quite left-of-center, politically).68
A lack of philosophical diversity in an academic field (always
leaning left in contemporary times) is usually understood to be
leading higher-level social sciences (with direct connections to, and
implications for, politics) such as psychology and sociology astray
from dispassionate science, but it is interesting to wonder whether
the discrepancy may have smaller effects even on as objective,
direct, and austere a discipline as physics.69
I claim that much of the
arguments in favor of multiverses boil down to instantiations of the
philosophy-of-the-gaps
fallacy: just because we don't know all of the limits of our current
understanding now, doesn't mean that we never will, and that we can
assume a naive interpretation of our current theories' mathematical
solutions as all being manifest in a multiverse.70
Ignorance can be temporary, but it doesn't have to be.
Footnotes
1. Funny enough, while looking for citations for
this essay, I came across passages I had read and forgotten, and
inside of them I found astrophysicist Adam Becker writing about a,
“profusion of worlds”, What Is Real? by
Adam Becker (2018) (pp. 256), and evolutionary biologist Richard
Dawkins writing, “a plethora of universes,” The God
Delusion by Richard Dawkins
(2006 / 2008) (pp. 175). I had recently been deciding whether to
entitle this collection of essays “A Profusion Of Place” or “A
Plethora Of Place”, I believed independently.
2. I am inspired here by Economist Eric Weinstein
having had the courage to point out that the following is an obvious
question (that is often neglected by teachers): “What is the
universe expanding into?”, “Joe Rogan Experience #1203 – Eric
Weinstein”, uploaded by PowerfulJRE (2018) (42:28)
(https://youtu.be/X9JLij1obHY?t=2548).
Thanks to PodScribe for helping me locate this passage
(https://podscribe.app/feeds/http-joeroganexpjoeroganlibsynprocom-rss/episodes/664ea75440dc4ec486a4e72d852a51ad#00:48:44
).
3. Quantum foundations will be the specific topic
of Part III of the present work.
4. Inflationary cosmology will be the specific
topic of Part II of the present work.
5. The relationship between physics and mathematics
will be the specific topic of Part IV of the present work.
6. Our
Mathematical Universe by Max
Tegmark (2014) (pp.
100-101, 103, 111-113). To be fair, Tegmark does admit that
inflation still may not be correct or may not be eternal, Our
Mathematical Universe (pp. 126).
7. This Russian-stacking-doll quality is mentioned
by Tegmark, Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
328).
8. Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
152). Tegmark even describes the previous expansion of our
understanding of the scale of the universe by saying it “pales in
comparison” to those he will describe, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 6-7).
9. Cosmos by
Carl Sagan (1980) (pp. 2).
10. This kind of “expansion” of the observable
universe is not to be
confused with the real (or
metric)
expansion of the entire universe
as a whole (the idea that space itself is stretching ever more). The
“expansion” of the particle horizon is a simple consequence of
the fact that we exist in a particular location at a particular time
and that there is a finite speed of light. Light traveling at this
maximum speed from far enough away in the universe hasn't reached us
yet, but every moment that ticks by, more of it does reach us than
before, Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
126). This just means that more of the universe (that already
exists) can be observed by us as we move into the future.
11. Astronomer Sir
Martin Rees points out that the “observable universe” is
simply a reference frame inside of the universe itself in his essay,
“Multiverse”, This Idea Is Brilliant edited
by John Brockman (2018) (pp. 136).
12. On
the (in)divisibility of atoms, Cosmos (pp.
188, 233). “... I prefer to use 'Cosmos' for everything,
and 'Universe' for the only one we can know about.”, Pale Blue
Dot by Carl Sagan (1994) (pp.
36). Physicist Leonard Susskind calls the whole of reality, the
“megaverse”, The God Delusion (pp.
173).
13. Our Mathematical Universe
(pp. 120).
14. From Lloyd's essay, “The Universe”, This
Idea Must Die edited by John
Brockman (2015) (pp. 12).
15. Tegmark admits the infinities are just an
assumption of the Big Bang model, and that space may be finite, but
also suggests theory predicts infinite space, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 17, 33, 97, 126).
16. It has become tradition (at worst, an arms race)
for astronomers to invoke The Copernican Principle and admonish
humans for thinking themselves particularly special in this universe.
This is put best by Sagan, in which it is simply a poetic warning
against anthropocentrism, but coming from Tegmark and many others, it
feels a bit on-the-nose and as though it's simply ticking off a box.
The Copernican Principle is also known as The Principle Of
Mediocrity, Science In The Soul by
Richard Dawkins (2017) (pp. 193, 195), which is a re-printed essay
entitled “Intelligent Aliens” from Intelligent Thought:
Science Versus The Intelligent Design Movement
edited by John Brockman (2006) (though I have not read this book).
Tegmark notes that some see the assumption of an infinite universe as
justified by The Copernican Principle, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 129).
17. Tegmark tries to claim
the CMB
data points to an infinite space-time because it points to a flat
space-time, but in reality, it doesn't necessarily point to
either—cosmologist Andrei Linde (a father of inflationary
cosmology) only even mentions the theory as solving why the universe
is uniform
(though to be fair, it's a short essay whose core thesis is in favor
of infinite multiverses) in his essay (against the idea of), “The
Uniformity And Uniqueness Of The Universe” in This
Idea Must Die
(pp. 44-45).
18. Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
127).
19. Tegmark
mentions the purported 'loss of determinism', Our
Mathemaitcal Universe (pp. 123).
By Tegmark's calculations, one would be expected to need a
level-I multiverse containing somewhere around 101029 universes to
have a doppelganger of oneself out there, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 119).
20. Namely, that, “... Despite their seductive
allure, we have no direct observational evidence for either the
infinitely big or the infinitely small. We speak of infinite volumes
with infinitely many planets, but our observable universe contains
only about 1089 objects (mostly photons). If space is a true
continuum, then to describe even something as simple as the distance
between two points requires an infinite amount of information,
specified by a number with infinitely many decimal places... we don't
need the infinite to do physics. Our best computer simulations,
accurately describing everything from the formation of galaxies to
tomorrow's weather to the masses of elementary particles, use only
finite computer resources by treating everything as finite. So if we
can do without infinity to figure out what happens next, surely
nature can, too—in a way that's more deep and elegant than the
hacks we use for our computer simulations.”, which comes from his
essay “Infinity”, This Idea Must Die (pp. 50-51). I would
only push back on this by wondering if the assumption of infinity
inherent to calculus isn't still hiding somewhere in our logic of
“limits” as variables approach certain values, even inside of the
approximation methods used in computers. To put a point on the
internal contradictions in the present book, Tegmark also mentions
that he doesn't believe there
are infinitely many objects (despite spending most of the book
arguing in favor of just this), Our Mathematical Universe
(pp. 316). Like any good
scientist, I suspect he is able to hold mutually exclusive possible
hypotheses branching in different directions until one becomes
evident, but it is strange to hear him forcefully argue that
contradictory sides are already
evident, say that he believes these mutually exclusive claims, or say
that he would place huge bets on some of these claims, only to
contradict them, seemingly without noting the tension, Our
Mathematical Universe (pp. 194,
196, 220, 319, 343, 361).
21. The Elegant Universe
by Brian Greene (2003) (pp. 118, 344).
22. Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
119, 124, 361).
23. He does also mention the step, “Compare
observations with predictions, update assumptions.”, Our
Mathematical Universe (pp. 300).
24. I use “agnostic” as synonymous with
“equipoise” (not yet known), and not in the classical
mysterianism sense as to mean unknowable in principle, as in
physician and social scientist Nicholas Christakis' essay
“Equipoise”, This Idea Is Brilliant (pp.
303-305). That said, I don't necessarily use either to mean
that I judge the different possibilities to be truly equally
likely; that's what long-form argument is for.
25. Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
19, 33, 138). Astrophysicist Neil deGrasse Tyson entertains
similar appeals, Astrophysics For People In A Hurry
(2017) (pp.89, 205). As does Rees, though to his credit, he admits
it would simply be an “intellectual and aesthetic upside” to a
separately proven multiverse, not a strong argument in its favor a
priori, in his essay, “Mutliverse”, This Idea Is
Brilliant (pp. 138).
26. Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
139). Tegmark notes that physical cosmologists (“... Paul
Davies, Brandon Carter, Bernard Carr, Martin Rees, John Barrow, Frank
Tipler, Steven Weinberg...”) first argued for fine-tuning in the
1970's and 1980's, Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
142). The earliest recordings of an infinite universe
hypothesis that I know of (with an understanding of the attendant
consequence that everything possible
actually occurs somewhere in this universe) and a primitive
type of Anthropic Principle (unless I am reading too much into
philosopher and historian Anthony Gottlieb's editorializing) come
from ancient Greeks Leucippus and Democritus around the fourth or
fifth century, B.C., The Dream Of Reason by
Anthony Gottlieb (2000 / 2016) (pp. 64, 109).
27. Our
Mathematical Universe (pp.
352). The Anthropic Principle is also known as The
Self-Selection Principle,
Science
In The Soul (pp.
193, 195), which is a re-printed essay entitled “Intelligent
Aliens” from Intelligent
Thought.
He also notes it is originated by “... mathematician Brandon
Carter in 1974, and expanded by physicists John Barrow and Frank
Tipler... ”, and that Carter ultimately preferred it be called The
Cognizability Principle,
The
God Delusion
(pp. 162, 440), further citing “The anthropic principle and its
implications for biological evolution” (1983) by Brandon Carter and
The
Anthropic Cosmological Principle by
John Barrow and Frank Tipler (1988) (though I have read neither
work). There exists a distinction between a weak (the naked
statement that living beings must find themselves in a region of the
Cosmos conducive to life) and strong (justification for a multiverse)
version of The Anthropic principle; the latter is the one I complain
about in the present work, A
Brief History Of Time by
Stephen Hawking (1988 / 1996) (pp. 128-129) and Pale
Blue Dot (pp.
30-31). Dawkins (and Tegmark) further make a distinction between
“planetary” and “cosmic” versions, as we already know about
the near-infinite variety of planets in the universe (whereas I am
presently arguing that a variety of universes is far from
evident)—this means that The Anthropic Principle is trivially true
in the planetary case (in fact, the strong and weak Anthropic
Principle are one and the same for the planetary version), The
God Delusion
(pp. 162-164, 169-170, 172, 174), and Our
Mathemaitcal Universe (pp.
145). As a less anthropocentric example
of The Anthropic Principle (linguistic irony noted), Tegmark claims
the masses of fermions look random, and therefore if you demand a
deep explanation of these physical constants, you must assume that
they're a random sample from other realities, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 147).
28. Sagan makes
(perhaps too) much of the uneasy relationship between The Copernican
Principle and The Anthropic Principle, and laments that The Anthropic
Principle is too presumptuous, Pale Blue Dot (pp.
33-34). By contrast, Rees sees multiverses generally (as regarded in
eternal inflation models, The
Anthropic Principle aside) as the next step in
The Copernican Principle playing
out (see footnote 16,
above), in his essay, “Multiverse”, This Idea Is
Brilliant (pp. 138). Physicist
Lawrence Krauss is sympathetic to multiverses hypotheses motivated by
something other than
fine-tuning / The Anthropic Principle, seeing these as violating The
Copernican Principle in his essay (against the idea that) “The Laws
Of Physics Are Predetermined”, This Idea Must Die (pp.
54). As Tegmark points out, physicist George Ellis actually
both warned that proponents of The Anthropic Principle / fine-tuning
may be making too many assumptions, and that multiverse arguments
could be a slippery slope to more
and more multiverse “explanations” (which Tegmark seems to have
taken as a challenge), Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
361, 363), which further cites “Does The Multiverse Really Exist?”
by George Ellis (2011)
(https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/does-the-multiverse-really-exist/)
(though I have not yet read this).
For this reason, that one can “explain” anything with The
Anthropic Principle, cosmologist Paul Steinhardt calls these,
“Theories of Anything,” This Idea Must Die (pp.
56). Mathematical physicist Peter Woit shares this sentiment,
claiming too many physics ideas now follow a paradigm of “anything
goes” in his essay (against the idea of), “The 'Naturalness'
Argument”, This Idea Must Die (pp.
70). Tegmark notes that for his work on the eternal inflationary
multiverse, physicist Eddie Farhi calls father of inflationary
cosmology, Alan Guth, “The Enabler”, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 150). For his
part, Tegmark thinks that figuring out how to retire the idea of
infinity from mathematics may tame the unwieldy consequences of these
infinite multiverses in his essay, “Infinity”, This
Idea Must Die (pp. 48).
Mathematical physicist Roger Penrose laments the laziness of the
Anthropic Principle standing in for real progress, as well, Fashion,
Faith, and Fantasy by Roger
Penrose (2016) (pp. 322). Cosmologists Neil Turok and Paul
Steinhardt also make the complaint that The Anthropic Principle /
fine-tuning multiverse both makes too many assumptions and sets a bad
precedent for failing to actually answer questions, Endless
Universe by Neil Turok and Paul
Steinhardt (2007)
(pp. 222, 232, 235-236, 250).
Mathematician Marcus du Sautoy makes fairweather remarks about The
Anthropic Principle being “... a bit of a cop-out.”, The
Great Unknown by Marcus du
Sautoy (2016) (pp. 222). Although astrophysicist Stephen Hawking
bought that the physical constants appear “fine-tuned”, he
nevertheless appears to have thought that strong Anthropic Principle
multiverses were an unsatisfying explanation, A Brief
History Of Time (129-131, 137).
Dawkins claims Susskind buys the fine-tuning / Anthropic Principle
multiverse (and Dawkins himself is sympathetic to it), The
God Delusion (pp. 171-173).
29. Incidentally, Dawkins criticizes a movement in
the history of evolutionary biology he calls “mutationism”, which
neglected the importance of selection (somehow
imagining that the variety provided by mutation was enough to explain
biological observations on its own), Science In The Soul
(pp. 119, 143), which was
originally published as the chapter, “Universal Darwinism”, in
Evolution From Molecules To Men edited
by D. S. Bendall (1983
/ 1985) (though I have not read this latter book).
30. To be fair, evolutionary psychologists use the
similar heuristic assumption that at some point in the deep past,
there existed both those who did and didn't enjoy sex, but that over
time the asexual types were naturally bred out for obvious reasons,
Cosmos (pp. 29). But
evolutionists do not usually hold that this is literally true,
just that something like that
happened; some kind of selection among variety herded the gene pool
to today's observation being the norm, but it could have been
upstream from this particular trait, and without empirical evidence,
one cannot be sure which competing
alleles actually happened to manifest and be selected in or out.
(Incidentally, in this case, it is quite likely that the selection
for the enjoyment of sex did not occur on humans at all, but on some
long ago species that each species it evolved into inherited, much
like how our five fingers originated in the five-boned-fin of an
ancestral fish), Cosmos
(pp. 298). It suffices to say that, assuming infinite time (as
geological timescales are quite large), the traits we observe today,
about four billion years since evolution began, should be quite
adaptive among possible alleles indeed, as there was a lot of time
for mutation to create variety and selection to cull out the lesser
traits (although there was also significant time for the environment,
and therefore the selection pressures, to change)–Sagan mentions
the date since life began in Cosmos (pp.
27) and Pale Blue Dot (pp.
84). But this is not the
same thing as claiming that every possible organism with every
possible allelic trait exists at
the same time, and we just happen to be looking at the ones we happen
to be looking at.
31. Cosmos (pp.
29).
32. To be fair eternal inflation has an incredibly
speculative and hand-waving mechanism for the creation of multiverses
in the 'Big Bang phase transitions of parts of the inflaton into
universes with quantum random differences in their physical laws',
but still lacks any selection mechanism; every kind of universe is
generated, Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
111-113, 118, 134-136). Physicist Lee Smolin is an
interesting exception: he has the idea that black holes may contain a
kind of offspring-universe with slightly different laws of physics
than its parent-universe (mutations). Sometimes, those
offspring-universes lack the physical laws and constants required to
form their own black holes (reproduce), and this is the equivalent of
being selected out, The God Delusion
(pp 174-175) and Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
151-152). The result is much more universes with black holes
than without, and one can think of those universes with more black
holes as being more prolific, and their kinds of physical law
(phenotype) as being more common among universes by inheritance. One
wonders what the equivalent of death would be (cosmologists have
spent a lot of time pondering the possible ends of the universe, and
it is likely that different universes would embody different ends
that took different amounts of time to arrive). One obvious issue is
the question of what happens to the child-universes when their
parents die (they are in some sense contained within their parents,
unlike biological organisms)? The phenomenon of Hawking Radiation
tells us that on a long enough timeline, black holes are losing mass
into their (parent) universe and will eventually evaporate
altogether. This seems to break the biology analogy; why are younger
children dying instead of older parents, and being subsumed by those
parents? And The Law Of Conservation Of Energy tells us that
a closed system (such as a universe) does not create nor destroy
energy / matter. But if there were a multiverse, why might we not
see a singular universe as an open subsystem,
and the multiverse as the closed system, in which apparent violations
of the conservation law (which have not been observed) are actually
squared by the excess or missing energy being accounted for in some
other universe (in the case of Hawking radiation, one expects the
mass of the child universe to be reducing over time, being added back
into the parent—this happening would be an in-principle testable
prediction of Smolin's hypothesis if I am not mistaken). Another
question is whether the original common ancestor to all universes is
also a black hole. If so, inside of what? If the outermost universe
is a black hole, how is it Hawking radiating, and again, into what—if
it is into nothing, isn't this violating The Law Of Conservation Of
Energy and The Law Of Conservation Of Information? Isn't all
energy and information in the
universe leaking away, being slowly destroyed until there is
capital-N nothing? As we go further and further down the
cosmic rabbit hole, this seems to be a good time to point out how
highly speculative this hypothesis is: there is relatively
little actual reason to think that a universe can exist inside of a
black hole thus far, let alone any idea of how or whether the laws of
physics would be different inside of these. Still, its inclusion of
reproduction and mutation mechanisms for variety, and a selection
mechanism for the probability of finding yourself in a given type of
universe makes it a better model for The Anthropic Principle
applying than most popular multiverse hypotheses (but then we still
need totally separate evidence to see if it is true, meaning that
even here, The Anthropic Principle can basically only live as a
post-hoc observation, not support for a multiverse as it has
tended to be used).
33. In fact, given the number of possible genetic
combinations, it is known that not every possible human genome has
come into existence, and the theoretical ability to count such
combinations has caused nobody in the field of biology to take
seriously the idea that this is a prediction that each such person
exists somewhere—Sagan mentions the immensity of the number of
possible human genomes in Cosmos (pp.
33-34). Of course, this argument only gets worse when you take into
account all species (and possible species), which appear to be
effectively innumerable. Evolutionary biologists will sometimes
argue that individuals with genes for trait X out-competed those with
the allele for trait Y, but they're not actually sure
exactly which Y-trait alleles existed in competition in pre-history
(without empirical evidence for populations with competing traits
that go away when the new trait shows up, from, say, the fossil
record), only that X-trait genes proliferated at the cost of some
competing allele because they
functioned so as to increase fitness well enough to be present,
today.
34. “The Philosopher John Leslie uses the analogy
of a man sentenced to death by firing squad. It is just possible
that all ten men of the firing squad will miss their victim. With
hindsight, the survivor who finds himself in a position to reflect
upon his luck would cheerfully say, 'Well, obviously they all missed,
or I wouldn't be here thinking about it.' But he could still,
forgivably, wonder why they all missed, and toy with the hypothesis
that they were bribed, or drunk.”, The God Delusion (pp.
173).
35. The latter comes from the classical notion of
chance randomness arising from our ignorance of certain details
(pseudo-randomness), whereas the former is the much more modern
notion of chance as truly fundamental randomness, which, as I will
argue in a later essay, is not even likely in quantum physics, the
field that has delivered the biggest confusion of the last century.
Tegmark rejects the probabilistic view, seeing it is a cop out to say
'we just got lucky' or “It's just a fluke”, even while supporting
the arguably equally problematic statistical view, Our
Mathematical Universe (pp. 140,
142-143, 362). The best defense I could make is that I don't
believe in fundamentally random / probabilistic processes, as would
seem to be required to give rise to a universe (whereas the
multiverse could simply be the terminating starting point of the
Cosmos, with no mechanism having created it). But those who argue in
favor of the statistical view typically do believe
in fundamentally probabilistic processes (in quantum physics), apply
those principles to cosmology, and tend to believe in a mechanism for
creating the multiverse (eternal inflation, quantum measurement,
etc.), so they cannot really justify choosing a statistical
interpretation over a probabilistic one; they do so because they
already assume a multiverse through other means (which again, renders
the fine-tuning / Anthropic Principle multiverse as trivially true,
rather than an argument in favor of a multiverse in the first place).
36. Cognitive
scientist Steven Pinker (referencing The Fallacy of Fine-Tuning
(2011) by Victor Stenger) points
out this possibility, Enlightenment Now
by Steven Pinker (2018) (pp. 423). Dawkins also cites Stenger on the
topic, The God Delusion (pp.
170), further citing God, The Failed Hypothesis
by Victor Stenger (2008) (though I have yet to read either Stenger
work). String theorist Brian Greene notes this possibility as well,
The Elegant Universe (pp.
368-369). As does Dawkins, The God Delusion (pp.
173).
37. Ironically, most proponents of The Anthropic
Principle rely crucially on both down-playing the importance of
induction by empirical evidence (multiverses are often claimed to be
un-observable in principle) and a
need for a lame kind of almost-anecdotal empirical observation that
one finds themselves in this kind
of universe. This is the sum of a completely speculative multiverse
married with a banal observation of one's surroundings. Typically,
scientific explanation consists of a deeply vetted theoretical
prediction married with careful, statistical observational evidence.
38. Tegmark
explains how an underlying Theory Of Everything would tie current
partially disparate scientific theories together, Our
Mathematical Universe (pp. 257).
Interestingly, he also points to the fact that mathematical
equations usually have many different solutions, and does admit to
essentially interpreting this quality in fundamental equations (which
we do not have) as predicting those solutions really manifest
somewhere, Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
362). This doesn't strike me as entirely obvious, even in the case
of a fundamental equation (though I am sympathetic to the idea that
this fundamental equation may unambiguously constrain to one solution
corresponding to the universe we observe, I do not think this is necessarily required for there not to be a multiverse).
39. Keep in mind that when trying to evaluate these
parallel universes with different fundamental constants, it is still
usually assumed that they have the same fundamental laws, such
as The Law Of Conservation Of Energy and The Second Law Of
Thermodynamics (the law of increasing entropy). Why? If constants
are turn-able knobs, why not laws? Tegmark takes this seriously when
he goes ahead and predicts a (level-IV) multiverse where every
possible mathematical law governs things, but most physicists who are
okay with the former are probably not okay with the latter. This
strikes me as inconsistent.
40. “Some questions were abandoned as naive or
misguided, such as explaining the sizes of planetary orbits from
first principles, which was popular during the Renaissance.”, Our
Mathematical Universe (pp. 247).
41. So it is mostly, but not entirely true when
Tegmark writes (citing physicist Eugene Wigner) that
traditional physical laws “... give no information about why...”
initial conditions have their values, Our
Mathematical Universe
(pp. 339-340). Flying in the face of both this idea and The
Copernican Principle, data on exoplanets have shown our solar system
to be fairly abnormal—most star systems are multi-star systems, and
even our planets are somewhat abnormal: “Earth is an extreme world.
Of the thousands of confirmed or candidate planets astronomers have
discovered in our galaxy, the most common type is a world unlike
anything in our solar system: an enigmatic ball of either rock or gas
that is bigger than Earth, but smaller than Neptune... three quarters
of the worlds [the Kepler telescope] has discovered are this gassy
variety, a planetary type not found at all among our eight planets...
The findings fit nicely with theories of planet formation, which
suggest that planets above a certain size cannot be made of mostly
rock. The more dense material you pile on to a rocky planet, the
more it shrinks under its own gravity.”, “Neil deGrasse Tyson
Explains Multiple Star Systems” uploaded by StarTalk (2013) (at
1:26) (https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=aQrtz2-XWHA),
excerpted from “Cosmic Queries: The Sun and other Stars” (2013)
(https://www.startalkradio.net/show/cosmic-queries-the-sun-and-other-stars/
), and “Most Common Planets Are Weird 'Mini-Neptunes” by Victoria
Jaggard (2014)
(https://www.newscientist.com/article/dn24826-most-common-exoplanets-are-weird-mini-neptunes/), who in turn cites unspecified papers by astronomers Geoff Marcy
and Yoram Lithwick (though of course I have not read these).
42. Chaos theory is the
idea that there exist “chaotic systems”–systems which, even
given perfect deterministic laws (and so perfect predictability in
principle), nevertheless produce unpredictable outcomes in practice
because small perturbations in inputs to these functions lead to
drastically different outputs (small differences such as those
inherent in any practical measurement of an initial condition). As a
counter-example, in a non-chaotic system, inputting 1.000 and 1.001
might yield highly similar outputs—given f(x) = 2x, we would get
f(1.000) = 2.000 and f(1.001) = 2.002: very similar answers
(depending on what these numbers represent). For a great explanation
of chaos theory, see du Sautoy, The Great Unknown (pp. 21-71).
It is worth noting as well, that there may be many forms of alien
life (and physically possible alien life) which we do not
predict from our physical equations, and which might still (or only)
exist as parts of astrobiology even after changing the tuning of
physical constants; we do not have the tools to make much of the
predictions of these knob-changes, Pale Blue Dot (pp. 33), A
Brief History of Time (pp. 129), and Krauss' essay (against the
idea that) “The Laws Of Physics Are Predetermined”, This Idea
Must Die (pp. 54). Physicist Lisa Randall goes further, pointing
out that without the direct observational evidence of biology and the
abstraction of biological science, we would have never predicted
Earth-biology from our current understanding of physics
despite the fact that it must underlie biology, “Michael Shermer
with Dr. Lisa Randall — Dark Matter & the Dinosaurs (Science
Salon # 1)” uploaded by Skeptic (2015) (52:57 - 53:10). E. O.
Wilson calls this difficulty consilience by synthesis (as
opposed to consilience by reduction): the fact that it's
easier to tie sciences downward towards lower levels such as physics
after we've understood them in their own abstraction than it
is to predict sciences upwards above physics, via lower
abstractions (we know some scientific facts about sociology; try
predicting those from the pure quantum physics of many particles),
Consilience by Edward O. Wilson (1998) (pp. 73-78). Tegmark
mentions this difficulty as well, Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
257).
43. The Great Unknown (pp.
65-68), which in turn cites “The Three-Dimensional Dynamics Of The
Die Throw” by Marcin Kapitaniak, Jaroslaw Strzalko, Juliusz
Grabski, and Tomasz Kapitaniak (2012) (which I have not yet read).
44. The obvious criticism of this is that the
first-approximation of cosmology may be much simpler than other
subsystems (say, human development) within it, because it is just
such details that are ignored in the models (cosmologists tend to
look at the blunt history of the universe only in terms of a few
variables, such as temperature and entropy). The problem is that one
cannot claim that chaos theory does not apply to these simplified
models if they then make predictions about the emergence of biology
(as biology was omitted from the simple model so that
it would be simpler; complexity is being sneaked back in in
the last minute!).
45. In fact, Tegmark concedes
that some parameters don't require much luck at all, Our
Mathematical Universe (pp.
354). Perhaps these are simply non-“chaotic” variables in the
system.
46. The fact is that the large-scale emergence of
(first chemistry, then) biology is far downstream from small
differences in inputs to particle physics, meaning it might not be
surprising that it is “chaotic”. In fact, mutations can be
chosen by evolution by natural selection whose phenotype-mechanism
acts early, as during embryology, so that the mutation can have an
outsize downstream effect, The Extended Phenotype
by Richard Dawkins (1982 / 1999) (pp. 262). It is sometimes
exaggerated that given the same initial conditions,
evolution by natural selection would turn out different forms if
allowed to run again.
Of course, there would need to be changes in initial conditions
somewhere in the local universe, however subtle, for this to
occur—and the “subtle” part starts to sound like chaos theory.
See du Sautoy for a bit on a related debate in evolutionary biology,
The Great Unknown (pp.
58-59).
47. “... the dark
energy density... it's about sixteen orders of magnitude smaller than
one might naturally expect, yet changing it by even a percent up or
down dramatically reduces the amount of either carbon or oxygen
produced by stars. Increasing it by 18% radically reduces fusion of
hydrogen into any other
atoms by stars, while reducing it by 34% makes hydrogen atoms decay
into neutrons as their proton gobbles up their electron.”,
Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
354).
48. “Hard-nosed physicists say that the six knobs
were never free to vary in the first place.”, The God Delusion
(pp. 173).
49. This is not to be confused with the measurement
problem in quantum physics, which is about why we seem to see a
single random value from within a predicted probability distribution,
upon observation, Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
177).
50. Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
313). This alone seems problematic to me, and again, Tegmark
does go on to agree, making the plausible argument that the concepts
of infinities and infinitesimals are only approximations of very
large and very small values, not real quantities, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 316-317). Sagan
appears to implicitly take this view when he writes, “A googelplex
is precisely as far
from infinity as is the number one.”, Cosmos (232).
51. Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
313).
52. Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
220, 223-225). Becker also briefly mentions the possibility
of unification between classical and quantum multiverse hypotheses,
What Is Real? (pp. 256, 285).
53. According to Tegmark, Everett argued that the
probability density of the wavefunction (its “square”, or the
product of it with its complex conjugate)
gave the measure / weight of a parallel universe, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 222).
54. Please forgive me if I am wrong about this facet
of quantum physics being continuous, as I am still extremely early on
in my technical understanding of the subject. Tegmark does say that
quantum physics' wavefunctions are continuous (though I am not sure
if it necessarily follows that the probability distribution derived
from the “square” of that wavefunction is also continuous) in his
essay “Infinity”, This Idea Must Die (pp.
51). My understanding is that even in those situations in
which the outcome itself is entirely discrete, say the spin of a
particle which is binary (either spin-up or spin-down), an infinite
number of “superpositions” (or probabilistic combinations) of
these are allowed: (approximately) 0% spin-down and 100% spin-up,
100% spin-down and 0% spin-up, and all infinitely many rational and
irrational possibilities in-between. Tegmark argues that if the
quantum multiverse is related to the classical multiverse, then this
means that there exist not just the two universes in which the
particle is measured spin-up and spin-down, there actually exist
(potentially infinitely) many in both states, but that the ratio
between how many duplicates of the one outcome to the number of
duplicates of the other outcome satisfies the quantum probability. For
example, if the quantum probability is 25% spin-down and 75% spin-up, then there are three times as many duplicate universes with a spin-up
outcome than those with a spin-down outcome. The problem I am trying
to illustrate is that parallel universes come in integer numbers and
the ratio of duplicate universes to overall universes is then a
rational number—this can only tend to approximate the
case of quantum physics making a prediction of a probability
distribution with an irrational quantity as the probability—imagine
a case where the theory predicts a π-percent
chance of measuring spin-up and a 100 percent minus π-percent
chance of measuring spin-down. It would intuitively seem that there
could not exist an integer number of duplicate universes divided by
an integer number of total universes (the definition of a rational
number is that it is the ratio
of two integers) that could satisfy this requirement (unless
comparing the sizes of different infinities somehow allows for
yielding irrational numbers, but this may be a problem for our method
of comparing infinities, not support for the present multiverse
idea). There appears to be another less elegant complication: for
observables that have not yet been quantized, such as position, given
there is a large infinity of possible positions for a particle to be
in (most of them irrational), then how could one have enough rational
numbers (the infinite set of rational numbers is smaller than the
infinite set of irrational numbers) to assign probabilities to each
of the possible positions? It is worth noting that there are many
physicists who think that spacetime will be quantized, with the
quantum being somewhere around the Planck-length, a
theoretical small distance obtained by performing unit analysis
arithmetic on physical constants. The most popular such group are
probably the loop-quantum gravity
(the current major competitor to string theory for a theory of
quantum gravity) physicists.
55. This is probably the most common argument
against multiverse hypotheses among physicists, including Ellis, Our
Mathematical Universe (pp. 361),
which further cites “Does The Multiverse Really Exist?”;
Steinhardt in “Theories of Anything”, This Idea Must
Die (pp.56); Turok and
Steinhardt, Endless Universe (pp.
234, 250); Smolin in his essay (against the idea that) “The Big
Bang Was The First Moment Of Time”, This Idea Must Die
(pp. 33); and Sagan (characteristically more ginger than most), Pale
Blue Dot (pp. 34). Du Sautoy is
more hopeful that these multiverse hypotheses will eventually be
realized to produce empirically testable predictions (though I think
most detractors simply think these ideas should be taken less
seriously unless
and until they
do make measurable predictions—someone like Tegmark holds that
these parallel universes need not leave any observable signature for
him to already believe, right now),
The Great Unknown (pp.
220-221, 226). Physicist Joanne Baker echoes this sentiment, 50
Ideas You Really Need To Know: Quantum Physics by
Joanne Baker (pp. 155). Becker puzzlingly insists that scientific
hypotheses need not be falsifiable before maintaining that they do
indeed need empirical evidence for confirmation (implying he may not
fully understand how far the anti-falsifiability camp often goes in
eschewing the need for observational verification—again, Tegmark
claims to believe in these multiverses right now),
What Is Real? (pp.
260-264). He also claims that even Popper wasn't completely happy
with falsification, What Is Real? (pp.
260, 263). Along those lines, physicist Sean Carroll claims that
it's forgotten that Popper understood falsifiability to be the case
only “in principle” , and proposes that scientific hypotheses
must be definite (making quantitative predictions) and empirical so
that we can “fit models to data”, in his essay (against the idea
of) “Falsifiability”, This Idea Must Die (pp.
126-127). I endorse this, but I do not see why he is so adamant that
this is different from being falsifiable—if your theory makes a
definite empirical prediction, then measurement during experiment
will either be consistent with it, or falsify it (as currently
formulated). I have trouble finding a definition for “falsifiable”
that doesn't sound exactly like “makes definite empirical
predictions”. Like Becker, Carroll, Tegmark, and myself (although
I likely lean more in favor of needing direct empirical evidence than
they do), Rees takes the view that unobservable objects may well be
the real predictions of theories and cannot be dismissed out of hand
in his essay, “Multiverse”, This Idea Is Brilliant (pp.
137). Astrophysicist Gregory Benford offers that indirect empirical
evidence (such as interaction effects between multiverses) would
suffice in the essay (arguing against) “The Intrinsic Beauty And
Elegance Of Mathematics Allows It To Describe Nature”, This
Idea Must Die (pp. 471).
56. Tegmark mentions “human baggage” (while I
agree that language is a form of human baggage in this sense, I
disagree with him that anything outside of the naked
mathematics is, which I will expand upon in Part IV), Our
Mathematical Universe (pp.
255-256, 258-259). “... science is all about understanding
reality...”, Our Mathematical Universe
(pp. 300). Similarly, “... scientific theories... need to
give explanations, unify previously disparate concepts, and bear some
relationship with the world around us.”, What Is Real? (pp.
264).
57. Tegmark explains isomorphism as the mathematical
equivalence of models, Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
280).
58. Tegmark (who evidently doesn't like the idea
much) calls it the omnivision assumption,
though I am not fond of this terminology, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 363-364). The
opposite view, that there exist phenomena which cannot be observed
even in principle has something in common with another (I think
premature) idea: mysterianism (the
idea that the human mind is physically incapable of understanding
certain aspects of reality), “Michael Shermer with Colin McGinn —
Mysterianism, Consciousness, Free Will & God (SCIENCE SALON #29)”
uploaded by Skeptic (2018) (especially 13:40 - 16:45). Rees also
makes an argument for this in his essay (rebutting the idea that),
“We'll Never Hit Barriers To Scientific Understanding”, This
Idea Must Die (pp. 167, 169). I
am skeptical of the premature conclusion, but I must admit that it is
a strong argument that other animals' brains clearly cannot
understand certain truths about reality, and our brains were not
specially designed for understanding the entire Cosmos (there is
little reason to believe that even the smartest human has the
smartest physically possible brain in the universe), “Michael
Shermer with Colin McGinn — Mysterianism, Consciousness, Free Will
& God (SCIENCE SALON #29)” (especially 13:40 – 16:45), and my
cousin Frank Scales also mentioned this animal-brain analogy to me
before. Greene explains the possibility of hard-mysterianism (that
some facets of nature may be unknowable in principle, to any kind of
mind, The Elegant Universe (pp.
385). Tegmark does not seem to go as far as mysterianism in his
views, writing that the abilities of the human mind have been
historically underestimated (though,
similar to the historical induction argument that having tended to
underestimate the size of the Cosmos suggests a multiverse, this is
not evidence that our ability to understand will not terminate
somewhere), Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
19). Psychiatrist and philosopher Jordan Peterson writes, “...
it's not clear that [humans] have any real limits.”, 12
Rules For Life by Jordan
Peterson (2018) (pp. 296).
59. Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
124).
60. Note that for me, simultaneously not yet
believing something but taking it seriously only speaks to its
likelihood of being
absolutely true or false, given my knowledge. I invoke none of this
poppycock about “amounts of realness” wherein some things are
“realer” than others. Even Linde himself admits that the fine-tuning / Anthropic Principle multiverse cannot be directly
proved or disproved as
long as our best theory predicted unobservable universes, and he explicitly lays out what kind of theory would be needed to supplant
such a prediction: “... (1) invent a better cosmological theory,
(2) invent a better theory of fundamental interactions, and (3)
propose an alternative explanation for [the uniformity of the
universe and the particular values of the physical constants],” in
his essay (against the idea of), “The Uniformity And Uniqueness Of
The Universe”, This Idea Must Die
(pp. 46-47). Tegmark relays that Ellis notes that the incompleteness
of current theories may eventually discredit current multiverse
research, Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
361), which further cites Ellis' “Does The Multiverse Really
Exist?”.
61. “Neil
deGrasse Tyson Explains Gravitational Waves and Gravitons”, a clip
from StarTalk's “Cosmic
Queries: Gravity” episode
(https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=EH70kTm25Es
) (2014) (3:17 – 4:03). “Gravitational Waves
Detected 100 Years After Einstein's Prediction” from LIGO (2016)
(https://www.ligo.caltech.edu/news/ligo20160211
).
62. Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
5). “Gravitational Waves Detected 100 Years After
Einstein's Prediction” from LIGO (2016)
(https://www.ligo.caltech.edu/news/ligo20160211
).
63. Rees makes the same argument as Tegmark in his
essay, “Multiverse”, This Idea Is Brilliant (pp.
138).
64. Tegmark admits these multiverses are at least
partially “untestable”, and spends little time on experimental
proposals (yet does spend
time on BICEP-2's experiment being evidence for a multiverse, though
this famously and unfortunately turned out to be a measurement
fluke), Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
110-111, 125, 151).
65. “... the discovery that a physical parameter
seems fine-tuned to allow life can be interpreted as evidence of a
multiverse where the parameter takes a broad range of values, because
this interpretation makes it unsurprising that a habitable universe
like ours exists, and predicts that this is where we'll find
ourselves.”, Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
352).
66. The Elegant Universe (pp.
368). Greene goes on to point out that the conservative argument is
poised to make a comeback even in the case of a multiverse, “...
the conclusion that [a multiverse] compromises our predictive power
is far from airtight... if we unleash our imaginations and allow
ourselves to contemplate a multiverse, we should also unleash our
theoretical musings and contemplate ways in which the apparent
randomness of the multiverse can be tamed. For one relatively
conservative musing, we can imagine that... we would be able to
extend our ultimate theory to its full sprawling expanse, and that
our “extended ultimate theory” might tell us precisely why and
how the values of the fundamental parameters are sprinkled across the
constituent universes.”, The Elegant Universe (pp.
368-369, 385). Rees also argues that some fundamental laws would
still constrain the multiverse (with previously-thought physical laws
being more like “local bylaws”) in his essay, “Multiverse”,
This Idea Is Brilliant (pp.
136-137). To be completely fair, Tegmark seems to want to split the
baby between the two views, sometimes emphasizing the unwieldy nature
of multiverses, other times seeming to claim they're as austerely
constrained as classical physics (also utilizing the term “by-laws”),
Our Mathematical Universe (pp.
123, 138, 150, 320-321, 340).
67. For Tegmark's informal poll, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 228). “It
is no surprise that... professors lean left... One of the strongest
personality correlates of left-wing politics is the trait of openness
to experience, a trait that
describes people who crave new ideas and experiences and who tend to
be interested in changing traditional arrangements... Social
conservatives tend to... prefer things to be orderly and
predictable... and they are more likely to see the value of
traditional arrangements.”, The Coddling Of The American
Mind by Greg Lukianoff and
Jonathan Haidt (2018) (pp. 110), who in turn cite McCrae (1996), and
Carney, Jost, Gosling, and Potter (2008) (though I have not read
these papers).
Lukianoff and Haidt show that the left-to-right ratio in academia
went from 2:1 in the mid-1990s, to 5:1 in 2011 (with at least a
slight dip in the following few years), arguing that “The only
field among the social sciences that is known to have enough
political diversity to allow for institutionalized disconfirmation is
economics, where the ratio... was... four to one.”, The
Coddling Of The American Mind (pp.
110-111). One 2018 study (with data gathered in 2017, N = 8,688)
found that the overall Democrat:Republican ratio was 10.4:1, with the
lowest being Engineering at 1.6:1, Economics at 5.5:1, Physics in 6th
most politically diverse at 6.2:1, and Communications a whopping
108:0!, “Homogenous: The Political Affiliations Of Elite Liberal
Arts College Faculty” by Michell Langbert (2018)
(https://www.nas.org/academic-questions/31/2/homogenous_the_political_affiliations_of_elite_liberal_arts_college_faculty
) (note, I have not read this entire paper, and refer only to Figure
1, which is the chart of Democrat:Republican ratio per academic
field).
This “... particularly in fields that deal with politicized
content, can undermine the quality and rigor of scholarly research...
when a field lacks political diversity, researchers tend to
congregate around questions and research methods that generally
confirm their shared narrative, while ignoring questions and methods
that don't offer such support.”, The Coddling Of The
American Mind (pp. 112), which
in turn cites Duarte et. al. (2015) (though I have not read this
paper). In fact, even the students have become more left-wing over
time, “... roughly 20% of incoming students identify as
conservative, and that figure has held steady since the early 1980s.
Self-described 'moderates' made up roughly half of all incoming
students in the 1980s and 1990s, but that figure has been dropping
since the early 2000s—it's now in the low forties—as the
percentage of progressives (self-described 'liberals') rises into the
high 30s.”, The Coddling Of The American Mind (pp.
113), which in turn cites “The American Freshman: National Norms
Fall 2016” by Eagen et. al.
(https://www.heri.ucla.edu/monographs/TheAmericanFreshman2016.pdf
) (2017) (though I have not myself read this).
68. Becker
mentiones the ick-factor when he claims detractors find multiverses
“unpalatable” and not to their “taste” (Becker claims he can
dismiss any arguments from unfalsifiabilty as “ignorant” people
succumbing to what I'm calling the “ick-factor”, but I clearly
disagree), What Is Real? (pp.
260, 263-264). Carroll has lamented that some physicists' objections
to a quantum many-worlds multiverse are as weak as, “... I just
don't like all those worlds...”, “Episode 36: David Albert on
Quantum Measurement and the Problems with Many-Worlds” uploaded by
Sean Carroll (2019) (https://youtu.be/AglOFx6eySE
at 50:31). They (literally) both agree that this is not a good
counterargument, “Mindscape 59 | Adam Becker on the Curious History
of Quantum Mechanics” (2019)
(https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=em7dkYZTetE
at 1:04:42). Tegmark made mention as well, claiming many see
multiverses as “too weird to be real”, conveying either “this
makes no sense”, or simply “I hate it”, Our
Mathemaical Universe (pp.
152-153, 363). Lloyd wrote, “The promiscuous nature of the
multiverse may be unappealing (Willam James, who coined the word,
called the multiverse a 'harlot')...” (language that would
traditionally be familiar in a socially conservative political
conversation), in his essay “The Universe”, This Idea
Must Die (pp. 13). I should
note that I'm not aware of ever seeing so base an opposition to
multiverses (even if I may feel it
on some level), I mainly see opposition on the explicit grounds of
unfalsifiability. On the topic of these physicists' political
orientations, I think both would proudly agree they are
left-of-center. Being a fan of work from both of these individuals,
I have garnered my sense for their being left-wing from multiple
occasions, but again, as I doubt there will be a disagreement about
this claim, I will just provide a couple of examples. Becker has his
pronouns “he/him” in his Twitter bio, originally a way for
trans-people to assert their non-obvious pronouns, now used by
sexually unambiguous individuals to signify solidarity with
trans-people (and, I argue, a way of virtue-signaling one's
politically progressive bona fides)
(https://twitter.com/FreelanceAstro).
Carroll implied that he is not conservative during a discussion in
which he criticized both Fox News and the Trump administration on The
Joe Rogan Experience, “Joe Rogan on Fox News & Sean Hannity”,
uploaded by Joe Rogan and Anime
(https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=GOnhCiUpumc),
excerpted from “Joe Rogan Experience #1151 - Sean Carroll”,
uploaded by PowerfulJRE (2018)
(https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ZtxzMb9CpTM
).
69. For more on the history of the politically
left-leaning (even Marxist) bias of academics (of social scientists
in particular), and the consequential flaws in the research of their
fields, see the first third of The Blank Slate by
Steven Pinker (2003 / 2016) (pp. 1-135).
70. I have named this as a more general version of
the god of the gaps fallacy:
the observation that many religious arguments rely on placing god
just outside of current scientific
understanding (presently, god might be invoked to “explain”
consciousness)–ignoring that these types of arguments in the past
have placed god in areas now understood by science (evolution by
natural selection replaced biblical Genesis as the explanation for
where people came from, for example), The God Delusion (pp.
151). In the case of multiverses, some physicists are placing
multiverses in locations that are currently open questions in science
(such as why the fundamental constants have the values they have).
One might fairly defend this as one hypothesis among many, but there
is a peculiarity about this particular hypothesis: physicists who
endorse it regularly oversell the footing it is on, and many even
claim to already “believe” it as the correct explanation (rather
than remaining in equipoise until the evidence is in). Besides
Tegmark, Carroll has been known to describes himself as a “partisan”
of the quantum many-worlds multiverse, “Episode 28: Roger Penrose
on Spacetime, Consciousness, and the Universe” uploaded by Sean
Carroll (2019) (https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=DJADe-_dRB0
) (at 1:14:53). When Tegmark briefly lists Ellis' problems with
multiverse hypotheses, many of his main points boil down to the fact
that these physicists' evidence is dubious because they are
pretending all current theories are complete and can be trusted to
give an accurate prediction to such extreme questions as whether or
not there exist multiple universes, Our Mathematical
Universe (pp. 361), which
further cites “Does The Multiverse Really Exist?”.
Change Log:
ReplyDeleteVersion 1.01 3/22/20 8:57 PM
- Added byline holding the initial footnote (since it can't sit on the title)
Version 1.02 3/22/20 9:00 PM
- Changed the initial footnote to be the very first character, instead; I figure this can be a quirky feature of my blog
The above is to be interpreted as being about where the superscript "1" would be located, to direct you to the initial footnote right away.
DeleteVersion 1.03 3/23/20 1:34 AM
Delete- Changed the line-spacing to 1.5 and slightly increased the font-size | Thank you to the following blogger (http://randuff.blogspot.com/2011/05/blogger-changing-line-spacing-for-all.html)
- Fixed some missing newlines between what were supposed to have been separate paragraphs
- Introduced paragraph indentation
Version 1.04 3/23/20 3:27 AM
Delete- Now the superscript footnote labels link down to the relevant footnote, and vice versa, so that you can just touch the numerals to jump between the body text and the footnote section | Thank you to Ginny Mineo (https://blog.hubspot.com/marketing/jump-link-same-page) and PeggyK (https://support.google.com/blogger/thread/4853299?hl=en)
- Also corrected a "level-1" to "level-I"
DeleteVersion 1.05 | 3/28/20 11:24 PM EST
Delete- Fixed a typo "falsibiability" to "falsifiability" (thanks to my brother, Jake Gussman)
- Fixed a typo "puzzingly" to "puzzlingly" (thanks again to my brother, Jake Gussman)
Version 1.06 | 4/9/20 ~10:43 PM EST
Delete- Fixed "10^89" such that "89" is actually superscript
- Fixed "10^10^29" such that "10" is actually superscript and "29" is double-superscript
- Fixed an erroneously singular "doppelganger universe" to "doppelganger universes"
- Removed an erroneous initial space from a quotation
- Corrected "footnote xvi" to "footnote 16"
- Corrected singular "selection and mutation portion" to "selection and mutation portions"
- For consistently, updated "The Conservation Of Information" to "The Law Of Conservation Of Information"
- Corrected erroneous page number "1412" to "142"
- For clarity, changed "it's necessarily required for there not to be a multiverse" to "this is necessarily required for there not to be a multiverse"
- For clarity, changed "as a possible alternative for" to "as a possible alternative explanation for"
- For clarity, changed "satisfies the probability" to "satisfies the quantum probability"
- For clarity, changed "is 25% spin-down, 75% spin-up, there are three times as many" to "is 25% spin-down and 75% spin-up, then there are three times as many"
- Changed "pi" to the actual pi symbol: π (which I copied and pasted from the right-hand bar labeled "Greek Alphabet" in the "Pi (Letter)" (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Pi_(letter))
- De-italicized "Karl"
- Changed the single instance of "Fine-Tuning" to "fine-tuning", as it is not a law, principle, or formal conjecture
- For clarity, changed "and explicitly lays out" to "and he explicitly lays out"
Note: These were found during a read-through process as I work towards video (and audio) versions of this blog.
Note: just made the change such that my own views are not counted as page-views (it does not appear to be the case that this subtracts my previous page-views prior to this moment).
DeleteThis is deeply interesting material to me more on the footing of what it says about the cracks in the social/political system surrounding science and how that can pervert the method itself.
ReplyDeleteAs for the topic itself I find it somewhat compelling though it is a topic that I must build my way up to. I'm not privy to enough of the prerequisites on quantum physics and the multiverse problem to truly make significant comment yet on the issue. This is not an introductory piece to this topic but it appears it could be a meaningful opinion and a genuine contribution to the argument.
Thank you, brother!
DeleteTO-DO:
ReplyDelete- Add in subtitle to the first citation of a work
- Add in publisher to the first citation of a work
- Unify formatting: parentheses for a citation out from the main body, commas for one inside of parentheses / made out from the footnote itself
10/19/22 4:15 PM
Delete- I should note that Dawkins does see 'god-of-the-gaps' as a special case of 'arguments from present ignorance' (concerning footnote 70 above).
(Interestingly, he also goes into how complexity is in-principle reducible, and how mystics fetishize mystery whereas scientists chase it so as to *answer* the mystery'--useful information for the book I'm currently publishing, piecemeal).
To whom it may concern,
ReplyDeleteI have been working for about a year on a cosmology paper, but in light of the recent JWST data release (which I was hoping to anticipate, and which I have not yet seen), I am going to publish the basic hypotheses and predictions, here, without the technical complications and citations which are slowing down the in-progress, and still in-coming, paper.
- If universes are contained in black holes, then the inflationary epoch is the small but rapidly growing black hole at the center of a star collapsing into a stellar-mass black hole
- This naturally transitions to a much longer accelerated expansionary epoch as the black hole consumes CMB proportional to its surface area (which grows with consumption of said energy in an accelerated feedback loop)
-- Perhaps JWST can more accurately measure the density of the universe during different epochs, as this hypothesis predicts that a black-hole-universe's density drops with the square of the radius (because it gains CMB energy proportional to the surface area as it expands), rather than classically dropping with the cube of the radius
- This then predicts a final, longer-still collapse phase (due to Hawking radiation) in which the universe also loses energy to its parent universe, culminating in a big crunch (Hawking evaporation) at a calculable future point
- Further, the medium length linear expansion phase between our inflationary and accelerated expansion epochs may be explained by the initial competition between CMB-consumption-growth (which is relatively weak early on, since the universe's surface area is low) and the Hawking-radiation-contraction (which is relatively strong since the power of Hawking radiation is inversely proportional to size); the growth soon wins out and the Hawking-radiation becomes negligible during accelerated expansion, until the temperature of the outer expanding universe is so low that growth is outcompeted by contraction
- My (likely flawed) preliminary calculations find that it is unlikely that this is the case--the correct values that correspond to our cosmological epochs do not seem to correspond by order-of-magnitude. Nevertheless, most important is empirical falsification of the density of the universe dropping as the square of the radius, rather than the cube. A flawed calculation comparing densities at different epochs seemed inconclusive but to slightly favor falsifying the black-hole-as-universe hypothesis, but I was hoping JWST may offer better evidence to work with
Sincerely,
Steven Gussman
P.S. There, now I perhaps feel I have got the burden off my chest, and my general predictions publicly logged. Perhaps now I can enjoy the JWST, and feel less anxious about the completion and publication of my paper! Or do I feel worse and more rushed to get my calculations and elaborations out?